It ed sorts of arguments against the thesis that constitution is identity apply in such per case

It ed sorts of arguments against the thesis that constitution is identity apply in such per case

Some philosophers find it important or at least expedient onesto frame the issue mediante terms of the case of per statue \(s\) and piece of clay \(c\) that coincide throughout their entire existence. We bring both \(c\) and \(s\) into existence by joining two other pieces of clay together, or we do something else that guarantees total coincidence. It seems that total coincidence is supposed puro lend plausibility esatto the claim that, per such verso case at least, constitution is identity (and hence NI is false – Gibbard 1975). For example, \(s\) may be admired for its aesthetic traits, even long after it ceases puro exist, but this need not be true of \(c\). And \(s\) has the property, which \(c\) lacks, of being destroyed if squeezed into per ball. Those who defend the thesis that constitution is identity need to defend it in the general case of partial coincidence; and those who attack the thesis do so with arguments that rete informatica equal well against both total and partial coincidence. The assumption that \(s\) and \(c\) are totally coincident is therefore inessential.

The doctrine of temporal parts offers only limited help. The statement that \(c\) is identical esatto \(s_1\)on day 1 but identical onesto \(s_2\) on day 2 can be construed puro mean that \(c\) is verso temporally extended object whose day 1 stage is identical puro \(s_1\) and whose day 2 tirocinio is identical preciso \(s_2\). Similarly, we can regard \(s_2\) as per temporally extended object that overlaps \(c\) on day 2 and \(c’\) on day 3. But unless temporal parts theorists are prepared esatto defend per doctrine of modally extended objects – objects extended through possible worlds analogous onesto objects extended mediante time, there remains per problem. \(s_2\) might have been made of verso different piece of clay, as is per fact the case on day 3. That is, it is logically possible for \(s_2\) to fail esatto coincide with the day 2 stage of \(c\). But it is not logically possible for the day 2 stage of \(c\) sicuro fail onesto coincide with itself.

Since the two stages are not identical, NI does not apply

Lewis recognizes this difficulty and proposes puro deal with it by appealing to his counterpart theory (Lewis 1971, 1986, and 1993). Different concepts, addirittura.g., statue and piece of clay are associated with different counterpart relations and hence with different criteria of trans-world identity. The property determined by a modal predicate may be affected by the subject term of verso sentence containing the predicate. The subject term denotes an object belonging esatto this or that kind or sort. But different kinds or sorts may determine different properties (or different counterpart relations). Per particular, the properties determined by the predicate ‘might not have coincided with App wireclub \(c_2\)’ (where \(c_2\) names the day 2 stage of \(c)\) in the following sentences,

This has the effect of rendering modal predicates “Abelardian” (Noonan 1991, 1993)

  1. \(s_2\) might not have coincided with \(c_2\),
  2. \(c_2\) might not have coincided with \(c_2\),

are different, and hence (a) and (b) are compatible, even assuming that \(s_2\) and \(c_2\) are identical. (It should be emphasized that counterpart theory is not the only means of obtaining Abelardian predicates. See Noonan 1991.)

The upshot seems onesto be that that the advocate of the norma account of identity must maintain either that constitution is not identity or that modal predicates are Abelardian. The latter option may be the fruitful one, since for one thing it seems sicuro have applications that go beyond the issue of constitution.

Categories:

Sem comentários

Deixe um comentário

O seu endereço de e-mail não será publicado. Campos obrigatórios são marcados com *